Difference between revisions of "Peirce's law"

MyWikiBiz, Author Your Legacy — Sunday December 01, 2024
Jump to navigationJump to search
(workaround for messed up blockquote template)
(use $\,-\!\!\!<$ for the sign of illation)
Line 16: Line 16:
  
 
<center>
 
<center>
<p><math>\{ (x \prec y) \prec x \} \prec x.</math></p>
+
<p><math>\{ (x \,-\!\!\!< y) \,-\!\!\!< x \} \,-\!\!\!< x.</math></p>
 
</center>
 
</center>
  
<p>This is hardly axiomatical.  That it is true appears as follows.  It can only be false by the final consequent <math>x\!</math> being false while its antecedent <math>(x \prec y) \prec x</math> is true.  If this is true, either its consequent, <math>x,\!</math> is true, when the whole formula would be true, or its antecedent <math>x \prec y</math> is false.  But in the last case the antecedent of <math>x \prec y,</math> that is <math>x,\!</math> must be true.  (Peirce, CP&nbsp;3.384).</p>
+
<p>This is hardly axiomatical.  That it is true appears as follows.  It can only be false by the final consequent <math>x\!</math> being false while its antecedent <math>(x \,-\!\!\!< y) \,-\!\!\!< x</math> is true.  If this is true, either its consequent, <math>x,\!</math> is true, when the whole formula would be true, or its antecedent <math>x \,-\!\!\!< y</math> is false.  But in the last case the antecedent of <math>x \,-\!\!\!< y,</math> that is <math>x,\!</math> must be true.  (Peirce, CP&nbsp;3.384).</p>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 29: Line 29:
  
 
<center>
 
<center>
<p><math>\{ (x \prec y) \prec a \} \prec x,</math></p>
+
<p><math>\{ (x \,-\!\!\!< y) \,-\!\!\!< a \} \,-\!\!\!< x,</math></p>
 
</center>
 
</center>
  
<p>where the <math>a\!</math> is used in such a sense that <math>(x \prec y) \prec a</math> means that from <math>(x \prec y)</math> every proposition follows.  With that understanding, the formula states the principle of excluded middle, that from the falsity of the denial of <math>x\!</math> follows the truth of <math>x.\!</math>  (Peirce, CP&nbsp;3.384).</p>
+
<p>where the <math>a\!</math> is used in such a sense that <math>(x \,-\!\!\!< y) \prec a</math> means that from <math>(x \,-\!\!\!< y)</math> every proposition follows.  With that understanding, the formula states the principle of excluded middle, that from the falsity of the denial of <math>x\!</math> follows the truth of <math>x.\!</math>  (Peirce, CP&nbsp;3.384).</p>
 
|}
 
|}
  
'''Note.'''  The above transcription uses the "precedes sign" (<math>\prec</math>) for the "sign of illation" that Peirce customarily wrote as a cursive symbol somewhat like a gamma (<math>\gamma\!</math>) turned on its side or else typed as a bigram consisting of a dash and a "less than" sign.
+
'''Note.'''  Peirce uses the ''sign of illation'' “<math>-\!\!\!<</math>for implication.  In one place he explains “<math>-\!\!\!<</math>” as a variant of the sign “<math>\le</math>” for ''less than or equal to'';  in another place he suggests that <math>A \,-\!\!\!< B</math> is an iconic way of representing a state of affairs where <math>A,\!</math> in every way that it can be, is <math>B.\!</math>
  
 
==Graphical proof==
 
==Graphical proof==

Revision as of 15:20, 27 July 2009

Peirce's law is a formula in propositional calculus that is commonly expressed in the following form:

\(((p \Rightarrow q) \Rightarrow p) \Rightarrow p\)

Peirce's law holds in classical propositional calculus, but not in intuitionistic propositional calculus. The precise axiom system that one chooses for classical propositional calculus determines whether Peirce's law is taken as an axiom or proven as a theorem.

History

Here is Peirce's own statement and proof of the law:

A fifth icon is required for the principle of excluded middle and other propositions connected with it. One of the simplest formulae of this kind is:

\(\{ (x \,-\!\!\!< y) \,-\!\!\!< x \} \,-\!\!\!< x.\)

This is hardly axiomatical. That it is true appears as follows. It can only be false by the final consequent \(x\!\) being false while its antecedent \((x \,-\!\!\!< y) \,-\!\!\!< x\) is true. If this is true, either its consequent, \(x,\!\) is true, when the whole formula would be true, or its antecedent \(x \,-\!\!\!< y\) is false. But in the last case the antecedent of \(x \,-\!\!\!< y,\) that is \(x,\!\) must be true. (Peirce, CP 3.384).

Peirce goes on to point out an immediate application of the law:

From the formula just given, we at once get:

\(\{ (x \,-\!\!\!< y) \,-\!\!\!< a \} \,-\!\!\!< x,\)

where the \(a\!\) is used in such a sense that \((x \,-\!\!\!< y) \prec a\) means that from \((x \,-\!\!\!< y)\) every proposition follows. With that understanding, the formula states the principle of excluded middle, that from the falsity of the denial of \(x\!\) follows the truth of \(x.\!\) (Peirce, CP 3.384).

Note. Peirce uses the sign of illation “\(-\!\!\!<\)” for implication. In one place he explains “\(-\!\!\!<\)” as a variant of the sign “\(\le\)” for less than or equal to; in another place he suggests that \(A \,-\!\!\!< B\) is an iconic way of representing a state of affairs where \(A,\!\) in every way that it can be, is \(B.\!\)

Graphical proof

Under the existential interpretation of Peirce's logical graphs, Peirce's law is represented by means of the following formal equivalence or logical equation.

Peirce's Law Figure 1.jpg (1)

Proof. Using the axiom set given in the entry for logical graphs, Peirce's law may be proved in the following manner.

Peirce's Law Figure 2.jpg (2)

Equational form

A stronger form of Peirce's law also holds, in which the final implication is observed to be reversible:

\(((p \Rightarrow q) \Rightarrow p) \Leftrightarrow p\)

Proof 1

Given what precedes, it remains to show that:

\(p \Rightarrow ((p \Rightarrow q) \Rightarrow p)\)

But this is immediate, since \(p \Rightarrow (r \Rightarrow p)\) for any proposition \(r.\!\)

Proof 2

Representing propositions as logical graphs under the existential interpretation, the strong form of Peirce's law is expressed by the following equation:

Peirce's Law Figure 3.jpg (3)

Using the axioms and theorems listed in the article on logical graphs, the equational form of Peirce's law may be proved in the following manner:

Peirce's Law Figure 4.jpg (4)

Bibliography

  • Peirce, Charles Sanders (1885), "On the Algebra of Logic : A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation", American Journal of Mathematics 7 (1885), 180–202. Reprinted (CP 3.359–403), (CE 5, 162–190).
  • Peirce, Charles Sanders (1931–1935, 1958), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Cited as (CP volume.paragraph).
  • Peirce, Charles Sanders (1981–), Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition, Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN. Cited as (CE volume, page).

See also